首页 And Yet_ A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest

And Yet_ A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest

举报
开通vip

And Yet_ A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest And Yet: A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest Sidney Axinn Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 25, No. 1. (Sep., 1964), pp. 108-116. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8205%28196409%2925%3A1%3C108%3AAYAKAO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4 Phil...

And Yet_ A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest
And Yet: A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest Sidney Axinn Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 25, No. 1. (Sep., 1964), pp. 108-116. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8205%28196409%2925%3A1%3C108%3AAYAKAO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research is currently published by International Phenomenological Society. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ips.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Fri Apr 20 00:07:24 2007 AND YET: A KANTIAN ANALYSIS OF AESTHETIC INTEREST This paper develops a speculation on the psychological nature of the interest in a work of art.1 The position starts with Kant's analysis of human nature, and his distinction between the objectives of individuals and of mankind. By "Kantian" I mean that some of Kant's ideas are taken out of context and used for my purposes. This is not a complete exposition of Kant's own theories, but an effort to call attention to some- thing overlooked in his position. The second object is to explain certain common techniques for creating aesthetic interest and some properties of the aesthetic moment. I. A Definition of Man Let us explore the consequences of assuming that man, considered distributively, has contradictory intentions as his fixed nature. More exactly, man is taken to be an individual who has some intention for the contradictory of whatever objective he wants. (Of course, contradic- tion is a relationship between sentences: we call objectives contradictory if the sentences describing them are contradictory.) The Kantian pedigree for this view of man's nature is found in various stages in Kant's work on history,2 ethics,s and religion.4 One of the special properties of aesthetic interest can be seen as a consequence of this definition of man. In addition to having contradictory intentions as their essential nature, let us assume that humans know themselves to have contradictory inten- tions! Consider the spectacle that such individuals present to themselves. The author would like to express his thanks to the audience and the other speakers at the Aesthetics Section of the American Philosophical Association meeting in December, 1961, at Atlantic City. An earlier version of this paper was presented and benefited by the response of Dr. A. Tymieniecka, the commentator, and others present. In "Idea for a Universal History on a Cosmo-Political Plan," Fourth Propo- sition. Also in the Critique of Judgment, 83. Foundations o f the Metaphysics o f Morals. In the first two books of Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone. They see something that is apparently trying to move in opposite direc- tions; and yet, this entity does seem to have coherence. It is this spectacle that, by analogy, is projected in a successful art work: the spectacle of a single entity that suggests an interest in contradictory directions, and yet does not lose its impression of unity. If we temporarily ignore the first Critique and the more familiar for- mulation of his ethics, and instead follow the consequences of Kant's analysis of human nature in other places, we find ourselves with a per- fectly good explication of his concept of a "purposeless purpose." Kant again and again uses the phrase "and yet" at critical points in his ethics and religion (Und doch, doch zugleich, are liberally sprinkled in almost every section). Not merely a stylistic fixity, it is Kant's position that man has contradictory principles in him: reason and sensuousness, the cate- gorical imperative and personal greed. I will briefly mention a few pas- sages from his book on religion. (Page references are to Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone, Greene and Hudson trans., Harper, 1960. The emphasis is mine.) Kant says that man, "despite a corrupted heart yet possesses a good will" (p. 39). In another section, "Our reason com- mands us potently, yet without making either promises or threats . . . ." (p. 44). Still later, he holds that the only way that man can frame a concept of a moral disposition is by "picturing it as encompassed by obstacles, and yet, in the face of the fiercest onslaughts, victorious" (p. 55), "The idea d the highest good. . . c m o t be realized by man himself . . . yet he discovers within himself the duty to work for this end" (p. 130). The use of "and yet" is no mere coincidence or accident of the translations. It occurs at dozens of critical points, and it is usually essential to the thought. The conception of man as a creature who1 has contradictory intentions is not Kant's private property; it can be found throughout the history of philosophy from Plato's image of the horses in the Phaedrus to Schopen- hauer and Freud. In Kant the idea seems to have the most general for- mulation. Perhaps just one point of contrast with Aristo.tle should be mentioned. Aristotle also takes individual man to have both rational and irrational "elements" in his soul, but he takes the rational element to be the essentially dominant part.5 In Kant's position the contradictory tendencies are equally essential parts of the nature of the individual. From Kant's viewpoint, individuals participate in the history of man- kind, the pursuit of a rational universe. One is a member of mankind, and yet he is also a particular person, a combination of humanity and 5 ". . .the irrational element is in some sense persuaded by a rational prin- ciple. .." Nichomachean Ethics, I , 1103a. personality. Individuals are continually torn between their personal in- terest in pleasure and their human interest in mankind's rational progress. Kant asserts this in many places, (e.g., Critique of Judgment, #83). Because the individual has inconsistent dispositions, it is impossible for him to be satisfied. To be free of conflict is to be dead. Therefore, Kant challenged his reader to imagine a human who is happy over a con- siderable period of time. Individuals are both social and unsocial; they have both egoistic and moral drives; they wish to promote the advance of morality, and yet wish to satisfy only their own sensuous inclinations. This is the "one-many predicament" in which the individual finds him- self. 11. Aesthetic Interest and Its Techniques Art works. are efforts to objectify the individual's one-many predica- ment. One may agree with Aristotle's view that art imitates nature, providing one adds that the nature imitated is the psychological and metaphysical nature of the individual. Following Freud, the child/parent, child/family, and the individual/species relationships are each variations of the human onemany predicament. Art provides a way of thinking about such patterns without the immediacy that would cause guilt or confusion. An individual is a partial repetition of his parents; art objects permit one to study examples of similar repetitions impersonally. Freud alone takes us this far, but by generalizing within Kant's framework, we find a basis for understanding the aesthetic appeal of a wide variety of devices. The interest in objects that are reflected in water may be explained in terms of our interest in seeing two things that are almost but not quite the same. The tree on the shore has some obvious priority over the tree in the water; the image in the water is both the same and yet clearly not the same. The same psychological factors develop the interest in contrapposto in sculpture, in steps, in fire, smoke, in a play within a play, in the devices of poetry such as rhyme, alliteration, equiv- ocation, rhythm, and the refrain. A stairway consists of a series of steps each essentially the same size, and yet each a little further along on some scale. Smoke consists of something that is both material and yet not quite material. The interest in fire is, among other things, the interest in some- that is both very dramatically existing and yet continually changing (kill- ing) itself and already nothing. Kant mentions "the changing shapes of a fire on the hearth or of a rippling brook. . ." (Critique of Judgment, #22, Bernard translation, Hafner, New York, 1951, p. 81). In a play, we find ourselves watching something that is happening and yet not really happening. In a play within a play, we add to this the chance to watch people who are in the same position; that is, they are both aware and yet not aware that the play before them is real. When we find two words that rhyme, we find two things that are the same and yet clearly not the same. In alliteration, we again find words that are in one sense the same and yet in another sense not. To find two lines of a poem that rhyme is to find two things that are clearly different in one way and yet the same in another. The root of the interest in these devices is in the notion of the contradictory nature of the individual and his interest in objectifying (projecting) this nature in a way that preserves its dignity. These examples are taken from the stock devices of the history of art. I'm ignoring a host of questions about the effectiveness with which the devices may be used and the fatigue and boredom that follows some repetition but not others. My point is that here is a special kind of in- terest in what I am calling the "and yet" situation. This is a situation in which we find ourselves drawn toward a pair of somewhat different aspects of the same entity. For example, it may add to the interest of an object if we see it against strong back-lighting because the eye is drawn toward both the object and the light behind it. Again, the molding at the top of the wall gives us a chance to follow two paths, two patterns that are alike and yet not quite. Where we would have had only one line, formed by the wall and the ceiling, the molding gives us at least two lines, somewhat different. The argument here is that to have aesthetic interest something must both be and yet not be quite what it seems. Easel painting itself is an art in which the surface is known to be two- dimensional and yet may be employed to seem three-dimensional. We have an example of the same kind of interest in a highly polished surface that reflects something else; and yet we know that it's only a reflection. The appeal of water, again, is that it is both a substance and not a solid substance. Myths do and yet do not portray reality, and this seems to be known to the audience if they are successful as myths. For other examples, we might mention the Aphrodite (in the Metropolitan) that is obviously hard stone, and yet seems to be soft flesh. Also, the architeo turd technique of a stone column that shows "sag" and yet obviously hasn't sagged in centuries. Some of the special charm of poetry consists in the sheer fact of its condensation. It may carry a large meaning in a small space. . . a pro- jection of the hope of significance for finite man. The same kind of thing seems to be involved in the appreciation of simplicity in other areas, for example, in mathematical elegance. Visual arts occasionally gain special appeal on just this score. In miniatures, an extremely small object can express vastness. For example, Jan Van Eyck's "Saint Francis Receiving the Stigmata," is a mere five inches in height, yet it includes in a small part of its area a wide distant landscape. Kant explains that in the 112 PHILOSOPHY RESEARCHAND PHENOMENOLOGICAL sublime we find "boundlessness is represented, and yet its totality is also present to thought" (Critique of Judgment, gz2.3). Of course, the most typical human activity, work, is quite clearly an example of conflicting objectives. It seems to be both the bane of life and the only source of satisfaction; theologically, both punishment by God and yet collabora- tion with God. To repeat, the argument is that: 1) man is an animal that pursues conflicting objectives; 2) man is, consciously or not, aware of his contra- dictory nature; 3) anything analogous (isomolt-phic?) to man's nature may become a convenient and interesting projection of it; 4) aesthetic interest is the interest humans find in examples of unified conflict, the "and yet" situation. Perhaps "no man can serve two mastors . . . ." Certainly one cannot succeed in serving two masters, should they conflict. However, if the masters are the conflicting goals of human nature, one can't be satisfied without trying to serve two1 masters. The reward for trying is human dignity, but not success. Morally considered, the two masters are the individual and mankind. The poht to see for Kant is that it is necessary to try but almost impossible for anyone to succeed in being moral. The one-many predicament can't be solved but it can be formulated imper- sonally in art, permitting us to study variations of part/whole relation- ships without committing ourselves to any specific relationship to our parents, children, or group. 111. Commercial Art? If the previous sections are well-taken, it is impossible to have art genuinely integrated with an advertising or propaganda objective. "Com- mercial" refers to a well-defined objective; "Art" to an objectless moment, a "purposeless purpose." Art, then, is an essentially hesitant (therefore tragic) pose. It can hardly be made to express a single con- sistent message. In a portrait even the facial features may be in conflict; the eyes may look undecided and yet the mouth and jaw may look set. In Holbein's "Sir Brian Tuke" (Hans Holbein the Younger, Painting 65, National Gallery, Washington, D. C.), we have a portrait of a man with his hands tightly clenched, holding something, and with a faraway look on his face. His eyes are looking off into the distance, apparently only concerned with the future, and yet his hands show us that he is also at the same time very much concerned with the immediate moment. Are the hands and face part of the same man? The interest in the painting comes from the conviction that these are indeed parts of the same man, that he is caught at a moment in which he is concerned with contra- dictory plans.. . to ignore the present and again not to ignore the present. Rembrandt's "A Woman Weeping" shows us someone in the moment in which she has almost but not quite managed to stop crying. In the sculpture of "The Prisoner" by J. Greenberg, one finds an indi- vidual presented at just the moment in which he turns as if to try to stand up again against the bonds that are holding him and yet at the same time has just realized that it is useless to try again. One gets the sense of both contradictory intentions. If the previous examples are at all general, the techniques necessary for the unity of propaganda must fail aesthetically. A typical advertiser who wants to show a young lady chewing gum and looking as if chewing gum is the one and only objective in life, ordinarily chooses a cartoon, rather than a photograph of a young lady. No actual young lady can look as if her only objective is chewing gum and still look human. In a photograph or a drawing with "aesthetic interest," the y oug lady must look as if she both wants to continue chewiug that gum and also realizes at the same time that there are other and perhaps better things to do. Another example is a recent drawing of a young couple leaving the church in whish they were just married, and the slogan underneath reads, "And they lived happily ever after with Standard Brands." Only puppets could look as if their only objective at this point was to make sound investments. Actual humans, or drawings with aesthetic interest, must show some conflict over their next move. To have only one objective is to be either a machine or a monster. The commercial artists do manage to hold our aesthetic interest occasionally by devices such as the drawing of a young lady in a typical soft-drink advertisement that seems to show us an individual who would much prefer an alcoholic beverage. On the adjacent billboard, we may see a drawing of a prim and prudent young lady holding a glass of beer and yet looking as if she'd prefer a soft drink. IV. The Aesthetic Moment The aesthetic moment or mood is assumed to be the moment in which one both wants something to continue because it gives him pleasure; and yet feels that it must not continue because it is irrational. Kant says that there are situations in which ". . . the mind is not merely attracted by the object but is ever being alternately repelled, the satisfaction in the sublime does not so much involve a positive pleasure as admiration or respect, which rather deserves to be called negative pleasure" (Critique 114 PHILOSOPHY RESEARCHAND PHENOMENOLOGICAL of Judgment,#23). Of course, for many works, there may be no such single moment. As a familiar example, consider Tennyson's poem, "The Charge of the Light Brigade." There is a moment in which the reader feels both the pleasure in the unquestioning obedience of soldiers and would like absolute military obedience to continue because of the pleas- ure in contemplating it; and yet, at the same time, feels that it is in- human and irrational to have unquestioning obedience and that the entire circumstance rationally must not be allowed to be repeated. The moment at which one feels both the pleasure in the obedience and the irrationally of the circumstance is the aesthetic moment. Lest this sound out of place in a Kantian speculation, remember Kant's view that "Even in the most highly civilized state this peculiar veneration for the soldier remains . . . because . . . it is recognized that his mind is unsubdued by danger. . . . In the comparison of a stateman and a general, the aesthetical judgment decides for the latter. War itself, if it is carried on with order and with a sacred respect for the rights of citizens, has something sublime in it . . ." (Critique of Judgment,#28). (What a recruiting sergeant Kant would make!) The pyramids in Egypt can produce an aesthetic moment of this sort when one feels the force of the objective of eternal life, and yet the irrationality of that goal for man. A Greek statue of an athlete, a woman, or a god that is a perfect example of the type can provide such a moment when one agrees that perfection of type is the all-encompassing human objective; and yet, that perfection of type is a trivial objective. A Roman aquaduct as a symbol of civic virtue and a medieval cathedral as a symbol of anolther world can each provide us with a moment in which we agree that we are faced by an example of the proper human ideal; and yet we find ourselves disillusioned with it.6 The Renaissance version of individualism has left us with portrait painting that again makes us feel both the pleasure in pursuing individuality and the futility of such pursuit. In contemporary art, we are presented with materials that give us pleasure by themselves alone; and yet, at the moment in which we feel that texture, color or form
本文档为【And Yet_ A Kantian Analysis of Aesthetic Interest】,请使用软件OFFICE或WPS软件打开。作品中的文字与图均可以修改和编辑, 图片更改请在作品中右键图片并更换,文字修改请直接点击文字进行修改,也可以新增和删除文档中的内容。
该文档来自用户分享,如有侵权行为请发邮件ishare@vip.sina.com联系网站客服,我们会及时删除。
[版权声明] 本站所有资料为用户分享产生,若发现您的权利被侵害,请联系客服邮件isharekefu@iask.cn,我们尽快处理。
本作品所展示的图片、画像、字体、音乐的版权可能需版权方额外授权,请谨慎使用。
网站提供的党政主题相关内容(国旗、国徽、党徽..)目的在于配合国家政策宣传,仅限个人学习分享使用,禁止用于任何广告和商用目的。
下载需要: 免费 已有0 人下载
最新资料
资料动态
专题动态
is_015070
暂无简介~
格式:pdf
大小:412KB
软件:PDF阅读器
页数:10
分类:
上传时间:2013-07-28
浏览量:6