首页 The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach

The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach

举报
开通vip

The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological ApproachThe Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach The Quest for Consciousness: A Quantum Neurobiological Approach. Henry P. Stapp Theoretical Physics Group Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory University of California Berkeley, California 9...

The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach
The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach The Quest for Consciousness: A Quantum Neurobiological Approach. Henry P. Stapp Theoretical Physics Group Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory University of California Berkeley, California 94720 Introduction Christof Koch has recently written an extremely accessible book, The Quest for Consciousness: a Neurobiological Approach. It summarizes in a clear way the main known biological facts that seem particularly pertinent to the mind-brain problem, along with an attempt to understand these facts within the framework that he has been developing in collaboration with Francis Crick. This theoretical framework, although only one of many being pursued at present, is probably as close to main-line neurobiology as any. This article contrasts Koch?s way of accounting for certain time- related psycho-neurobiological data with a contemporary-physics-based understanding of these data. By a contempory-physics-based understanding I mean an understanding based on the fundamental principles of physics, as they are understood today by physicists. This understanding differs profoundly from the one that prevailed at the end of the nineteenth century. During the first part of the twentieth century it became clear that the earlier approach was conceptually unable to account for the results of the observations that we make upon systems whose behaviors depend sensitively on the motions of their atomic constituents. Physicists, lead by Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg, and Wolfgang Pauli, erected the new and empirically successful physical theory based not on the idea of evolving material substances, but rather upon the idea of a sequence of abrupt events. Each of these events is psychophysical in the sense that it has, on the one hand, certain aspects that are described in the ordinary language that, in Bohr?s words, we use to communicate to others “what we have done and what we have learned”, and, on the other hand, other aspects that are described in the mathematical language of contemporary physics. These psychophysical events link certain physically described aspects of the systems we observe to events in our minds. These mind-matter connections were subsequently converted by John von Neumann to connections between the minds and the brains of human observer-participants. This introduction, at the level of the basic physics, of events that relate physical descriptions of our brains to events in our streams of consciousness has led many physics who are interested basic ontological issues to the conclusion that twentieth century physics may provide the a more adequate foundation for understanding the connection between our brains and our minds than its nineteenth century predecessor, which treated our minds---our conscious thoughts---as passive, causally inert witnesses of certain aspects of the physically described world; as witnesses 1 having no conceptual or causal place in the causally closed physically described world. The older theory is an approximation to the contemporary theory, and this approximation systematically leaves out certain physical effects of our conscious choices that, according to twentieth-century physics, are a sine qua non component of the dynamics. This possibility that the inclusion of the mind-brain connection enforced by the basic principles of physics might offer a more rationally coherent and useful conception of the connection between our conscious thoughts and their neural correlates than the classical-physics-based ideas currently in vogue in neuroscience has recently been explored in some detail. (Schwartz, Stapp, and Beauregard 2005, Stapp 2004, 2005, 2007). The encouraging findings will not be reviewed here. However, readers of this article do need some general understanding of what is meant here by “orthodox contemporary quantum theory of the mind-brain connection”. Hence, before describing the contrasts between Koch?s explanations of the psychobiological data, and the contemporary-physics-based account, a brief description needs to be given of the significant contrasts between these two alternative theoretical frameworks. Contemporary-physics-based approach to the connection between mind and brain. It is by now widely appreciated that the materialist-deterministic conception of nature that prevailed during the eighteenth and nineteen centuries fails to account for the macroscopic properties of systems whose behaviors depend sensitively on the behaviors of their atomic-sized constituents. That earlier theory was replaced during the first half of the twentieth century by quantum theory. The basic mathematical change was to replace the numbers of the older theory by operators. The effect of this replacement is to change the theory from one putatively about intrinsic observer-independent properties of physical systems to one explicitly about the observed feedbacks from actions performed upon observed systems by observing systems. Observing systems that stand somewhat apart from observed physical systems, but that act upon them in chosen ways, and then receive feedbacks from them, are thus brought into the dynamics of the full combined system. The older theory, classical mechanics, has one single dynamical process, the continuous evolution of the physical universe in accordance with Newton?s laws, or perhaps some classical-type generalization of them. In contrast, the new theory, quantum theory, is built around a sequence of discrete events that is governed by four processes. Each such event is, from an ontological perspective, simultaneously: (1), an actualization of certain mathematically characterized potentialities created by prior events; (2) a creation of potentialities for future events; and (3), an experiential event that constitutes an increment in knowledge. One of the four processes governing the flow of these events is called by von Neumann Process 1. It is a mathematically characterized abrupt action of an observing system upon an observed system. This action has the effect of posing a particular question about the observed system. A second process, called Process 2 by von Neumann, is a continuous deterministic process. It is the quantum analog of the single deterministic 2 process of classical physics, but it acts only during the intervals between successive abrupt events. The third process is the abrupt event of answering the question posed by Process 1. It is called by Dirac a “choice of the part of nature”. It is random: it conforms to specified statistical conditions. This “Process 3” is where the famous “random element” enters into quantum mechanics. The fourth process is called Process Zero, because it comes before Process 1 This action is what Niels Bohr calls a “free choice on the part of the experimenter.” This choice specifies which particular probing action--- taken from among a host of allowed possibilities---will be instigated by the experimenter: it specifies which question will be posed, and when that question will be posed. This Process Zero choice is not constrained or limited by any currently known law, statistical or otherwise, and is treated, in actual scientific practice, as the conscious choice of a human agent. Because this choice is not fixed by any known laws it is, in this very specific sense, a “free choice”. Quantum mechanics is, in this way, explicitly about selected observations and their observed outcomes. Each such action is represented by abrupt event that suddenly change the physically described properties of the observed system in a way concordant with the associated increment of knowledge of the observer. In the von Neumann formulation the directly observed system becomes the brain of the observer, and the mind-matter connections of the original “Copenhagen” formulation are converted to mind-brain connections. This quantum understanding of nature is radically different from the earlier classical conceptualization, which has no conceptual or causal place for experiential realities. The quantum framework is more complete than the earlier classical framework, because it incorporates descriptions of both our physically described brains and the experiential realities that are causally connected to them, and it specifies the putative form of a dynamical connection between them. Both of these aspects of our understanding of nature are essential components of science, and quantum theory is expressly designed to bring usefully into science the fact that “in the great drama of existence we ourselves are both actors and spectators.” (Bohr, 1963, p. 15: 1958, p. 81) An important characteristic of this quantum conceptualization is that the substantive-matter-like aspects, have dropped out. The theory is about: (1) abrupt events, each of which is tied to an experiential increment in knowledge; and (2) potentialities for such events to occur. Events are not substances, which, by definition, endure. And the potentialities have an “idea-like” character because they are like an “imagined” idea of what the future events might be; and they change abruptly when a new event occurs. Thus neither the events nor the potentialities have the ontological character the substantive matter of classical physics. Yet the predictions of quantum mechanics encompass all of the known successes of classical mechanics. A second important feature of this quantum ontology is that the conscious “free choices” of which question will be posed next, and when it will be posed---neither of which is determined by any known law---can influence the course of the psychophysical events. The principle of the “causal closure of the physical” is therefore not enforced in orthodox quantum theory, not only because of the entry, via Process 3, of random elements, but also, and more importantly in the present context, because of the entry of physically 3 effective Process Zero conscious free choices. These latter choices can influence the objective potentialities for future actual events, and thereby affect also the course of actual events.. A third important point is this. By virtue of the quantum rules themselves, a conscious intent to perform either a physical action or a mental action (say to recall something or to focus one?s attention on something) can have, by virtue of a well known quantum effect-- -the quantum Zeno effect---the physical effect of holding in place a pattern of neurobiological activity that tends to cause this imagined, or expected, or intended experience actually to occur. Such a pattern of brain activity---namely one such that its persisting existence for a sufficiently long time tends to cause the (experience of the) contemplated action to occur---is called a template for action. How it comes about that conscious free choices can, by virtue of the quantum psychophysical laws, cause a physically described template for action to be held in place for an extended period has been described elsewhere (in most detail in Stapp 2004), and will not be reviewed here. The earlier articles, cited above, described many applications of twentieth-century physics to the data amassed in scientific studies pertaining to volition. The present article is an application to some data described in Koch?s book. Koch’s Quest for Consciousness and the NCC’s Kock?s title advertises his book as The Quest for Consciousness, and he speaks briefly, at the beginning (and also in several other places) about the mystery of consciousness---about the puzzle of why certain activities in our brains are accompanied by conscious experiences. But he says (p.xv) that “I argue for a research program whose supreme aim is to discover the neural correlates of consciousness, the NCC. These NCC?s are defined (p.xv: p. 341) as: “The minimal set of neuronal mechanisms or events jointly sufficient for a specific conscious precept or experience.” He immediately adds: “This is what this book is about.” Notice that he does not say “necessary and sufficient”. This means that he is not suggesting an equivalence between a conscious experience and its neural correlate. Indeed, he says explicitly (p. 19) “The characters of brain states and of phenomenal states appear too different to be completely reducible to each other.” Thus he distinguishes brain activities from streams of consciousness, and his definition allows a conscious experience to occur without the associated NCC occurring. He emphasizes, right from the start, that his book is about the NCC?s, not about consciousness per se, and he acknowledges that it does not address the big mystery of consciousness: why does it exist at all. In fact, he notes (p.334) that his project of identifying the NCC?s is what David Chalmers calls “The Easy Problem”. Chalmers argues that solving this East Problem leaves unresolved The Hard Problem of consciousness: “why does it exist at all”; the 4 mystery of why “the causation of behavior should be accompanied by subjective inner life.” Francis Crick, in his Foreward to Koch?s book, says simply that “our strategy has been to try first to find the neural correlates of consciousness.” [My emphasis.] But Koch says that “Characterizing the NCC is one of the ultimate scientific challenges of our times.” This apparent elevation by Koch of the first part of the attack on the problem of consciousness, namely the “Easy” NCC part, from preliminary to ultimate status is probably connected to his assertion that: “I suspect that the Hard Problem …will disappear once one has solved the Easy Problem.” (p. 334). Can we identify the root of this major difference between Chalmers? position and Koch?s? I think so! Chalmers, in his characterization of his position says. “I have not disputed that the physical world is causally closed or that behavior can be explained in physical terms.” (Chalmers 1996, p. xiii). But this puts him essentially in the arena of classical physics, where consciousness is epiphenomenal: where conscious can do nothing in the physical world not done by the physical aspects alone. Given Chalmers?s underlying acquiescence to epiphenomenalism, it is no wonder he encounters a hard problem. Koch seemingly adopts a far more reasonable position! He apparently believes that consciousness can have real effects in the physical world. “I argue that consciousness gives access to … planning…Without consciousness you would be worse off.” (p. 4) He asks “ Why then, from the point of view of evolution, does consciousness exist? What survival value is attached to consciousness?” (p. 2) “In a fiercely competitive world consciousness must give the organism an edge over non-conscious zombies” (p. 231) “Operationally consciousness is needed for nonroutine tasks…(p. 12).” “The belief that phenomenal consciousness is real but impotent to influence events in the physical world continues to be remarkably widespread among modern philosophers. While this idea cannot, at this point, be proved false, it can be undermined… (p. 238). Thus Koch appears to be saying, in many places, that, according to his thinking, consciousness has real physical effects. Presumably, his position is that consciousness itself is doing these things. No one doubts that neural activities, or brain activities, can have physical effects: the issue is only whether consciousness itself, which he recognizes as being inequivalent to brain state, can have such effects. If the NCC?s, and the entailed brain states, by themselves, were able to do whole job, then there would be no justifiable reason to say that (inequivalent) consciousness has important effects, particularly in this context where the connection between consciousness and brain states is a key issue. If Koch indeed believes that consciousness is not epiphenomenal---that it does things not done by the NCC?s and the physically entailed brain states alone, and hence can have an evolutionary reason to exist---then he is going outside classical physics, which, because it enforces the principle of the causal closure of the physical, cannot allow anything not equivalent to some physically describable property to have physical consequences. Thus when Koch claims (p. 11) that his non-epiphenomenal “conscious is fully compatible with the laws of physics” he cannot be referring to the laws of classical physics, because 5 classical physics makes consciousness, insofar as it is not equivalent to a physical property, epiphenomenal. Since he cannot, rationally, be referring to the laws of deterministic classical physics, he must be referring to the laws of quantum physics, which do allow our conscious choices to influence brain activity, without being equivalent to any physically describable brain activity! Koch?s explanations of the psycho-neurobiological data are in terms of the essentially classical idea of “victories of coalitions”. Thus his model does not appear to bring in the quantum effects that can actually allow consciousness to possess the non-epiphenomenal status that he ascribes to it. It must be noted, however, that Koch does not always maintain a sharp distinction between the effects of consciousness and the effects of its NCC?s. For example, on page 18 he begins, promisingly, with the clean assertion “As I shall argue in Chapter 14, it is quite unlikely that consciousness is a mere epiphenomenon. Rather consciousness enhances the survival of its carrier.” But he then immediately goes on to say “This means that the NCC activity must affect other neurons in some manner.” But this is a non sequitur if, as his definition allows, the conscious event is not equivalent to its NCC, and can occur without it. This basic conceptual problem (namely the epiphenomenal character of consciousness within classical physics) points to the logical need, if consciousness is to have survival value, and one respects the laws of physics, to bring into the model the quantum effects that allow consciousness to be non-epiphenomenal. The interesting question, then, is whether this shift, demanded by rationality, has benefits beyond its mere rationality. Differences between Koch’s explanation of some neurobiological data and the physics-based explanation Koch?s FIGURE 15.1B pertains to an experiment in which a subject observers a light source that is abruptly turned on, then maintained at a steady intensity for a certain interval, and then abruptly turned off. The figure shows a variable that Koch identifies as a “the „critical? activity at the essential node for brightness”. This variable rises with time until, at time T it reaches a conjectured threshold, Threshold. This variable then ON,on becomes an NCC, and it remains so until, at time T it drops below an OFF threshold, OFF, Threshold. During the interval between T and T this critical amplitude, labeled offON OFF NCC, varies greatly, but the brightness of the light is experienced as constant. But why is the experienced brightness zero before T then constant over the period between T ON, ON and T while the strength of the driving amplitude is greatly varying, and then abruptly OFF, zero again? One might expect, a priori, from classical physics, that if the presence of the experience depends on the strength of an amplitude then the quality of the experience should also depend upon the strength of that amplitude, and should therefore vary over a period during which the strength of driving amplitude is varying greatly. Why is this not the case? 6 Koch?s explanation of the empirical constancy is this. Coalitions of neurons, firing in coordinated ways, battle for supremacy. When some coalition reaches “some sort of threshold” (p. 253) it brings about coordinated firings in many parts of the brain “until a stable equilibrium is reached.” At this point an experience occurs. After a while, neural fatigue, and perhaps other factors, causes this state of stable equilibrium to break down, and the constant experience---say of brightness--- which has endured unchanging during the period of stable equilibrium, will abruptly cease to exist. This process, as conceived of from a classical point of view, is purely mechanical (i.e., neuro-physiological) with consciousness merely a consequence of the mechanically maintained state of stable equilibrium, not a causal contributor to the endurance of that state.. Once the macroscopic state of stable equilibrium that correlates with the experience comes mechanically into being it can become a controlling feature that can mechanically influence a lot of other brain activities, and one can say that the NCC exercises a sort of top-down control, which is correlated with the experience that this NCC is the correlate of. There could then be an “illusion” that the conscious experience itself is “causing” the activities that are actually being caused, purely mechanically, by the stable brain activity that is entailed by the varying NCC?s. If Koch adheres consistently to this position that all conscious experiences are consequences of physically describable activities, and that our intuition that our conscious events can influence physically describable activities is an illusion---that is, if he accepts that conscious experiences themselves have no effect on physically described activities---then he will be unable to rationally support his claim that consciousness aids survival: consciousness cannot aid survival if it can have no effect on physically describable activities. If, therefore, he accepts that conscious experiences can influence physically describable activities, yet are, as he admits, not the same thing as physically describable activities, he must, perforce, jettison the constraints imposed by the classical physical principles. Bohr (1962, p. 60), referring to discrete-event aspect of quantum theory, emphasizes: “The element of wholeness characterized by the quantum of action and completely foreign to classical physical principles.” Buds of Perception and the Wagon Wheel Illusion One of the chief features of (conscious) perception is its discrete “all or nothing at all” character. William James [1911] said of percepts that: a discrete composition is what actually obtains in our perceptual experience. We either perceive nothing, or something already there in a sensible amount. This fact is what is known in psychology as the laws of the „threshold.? Either your experience is of no content, of no change, or it is of a perceptible amount of content or change. Your acquaintance with reality grows literally by buds or drops 7 of perception. Intellectually and on reflection you can divide these into components, but as immediately given they come totally or not at all. A closely connected phenomenon was discussed by Koch in the same Chapter 15. It is the “wagon wheel illusion”. Every cowboy-movie goer is familiar with the fact that the wheels of a moving wagon sometimes seem to be turning backward. The explanation is simple: the flickering sequence of frames catches the wheels at times such that a later spoke has almost reached the position that an earlier spoke was at in the previous frame. But there is a related empirical fact the needs explaining: The same illusion occurs in broad daylight! At this point (p.264) Koch says “The implicit assumption up to this point has been that you and I experience the world in a continuous fashion: that the seamless nature of perceptual experience is reflected in the smooth waxing and waning of the NCC”. He goes on to say: “This is not the only possibility. Perception might well take place in discrete processing epochs, perceptual moments, frames, or snapshots.”… “Within one such moment the perception of brightness, color, depth, and motion would be constant.” Koch goes on to say “Plenty of psychological data favors discrete perception, with the duration of each snapshot being quite variable, lasting anywhere between 20 and 200 msec.” He cites an extreme example that was experienced by the neurologist Oliver Sacks. During a visual migraine Sacks did not see “movements as continuous but rather as a succession of “stills,” a succession of different configurations and positions, but without any movement in-between, like the flickering of a film … run too slow.” Koch?s explanation of the evidence in favor of discrete perception, in terms of what is going on in the continuously changing brain, harks back to his explanation of the constancy of the perception of the steady light. He says (p. 264): “Activity at the essential mode for some attribute would build up until a dominant coalition established itself and the NCC came into being. If the subject continued to attend to the stimulus, the dynamics of the system would have to be such that with some degree of regularity the NCC turn off and on again, constant within one perceptual moment but changing from one to the next before reaching a new quasi steady-state.” Koch?s explanation of this fundamentally bud-like character of perception depends upon some putative properties of the mind-brain, conceived of in classical mechanistic materialist terms that are known to be fundamentally false. On the other hand, the explanation of this discreteness within the framework of the principles of quantum physics stems not from conjectured special properties of the classical approximation, which eliminates all the physical effects of our thoughts, but rather from mathematical demands arising from the need to incorporate rationally into our understanding of all natural phenomena the profound effects of the quantum of action discovered at the end of the nineteenth century by Max Planck. 8 Accepting contemporary physics has the advantage of bringing not only perception itself, but also the bud-like character of perception into the theory at the fundamental level, and of also explaining, directly in terms of the basic known dynamical laws of physics, how consciousness can causally effect our physical actions, and thereby allow it to aid survival, as Koch grants that it does ___________________________________________________________ This work was supported by the Director, Office of Science, Office of High Energy and Nuclear Physics, of the U.S. Department of Energy under contract DE-AC02-05CH11231 References Bohr, N. (1934). Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bohr, N. (1958). Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. New York: Wiley. Bohr, N. (1963): Essays 1958/1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. (Wiley, New York) James, W. (1911): Some Problems in Philosophy, Chapter X, Novelty and the Infinite---The Conceptual View. William James: Writings 1902-1910. (Library of America, New York) p. 1061. Koch, C. (2004). The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. (Englewood, CO: Roberts and Co,) Schwartz, J, Stapp, H, & Beauregard M. (2005). “Quantum Physics in Neuroscience and Psychology: A Neurophysical Model of Mind/Brain Interaction,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 360 (1458) 1309-27. Stapp, H. (2004). Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics (Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer) Second edition. Chapters 6 & 12. Stapp, H. (2005). “Quantum Interactive Dualism: An Alternative to Materialism,” J. Conscious Studies.12, No.11 pp. 43-58. Stapp H. (2007). The Mindful Universe: Quantum Mechanics and the Participating Observer (Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer) 9
本文档为【The Quest for Consciousness A Quantum Neurobiological Approach】,请使用软件OFFICE或WPS软件打开。作品中的文字与图均可以修改和编辑, 图片更改请在作品中右键图片并更换,文字修改请直接点击文字进行修改,也可以新增和删除文档中的内容。
该文档来自用户分享,如有侵权行为请发邮件ishare@vip.sina.com联系网站客服,我们会及时删除。
[版权声明] 本站所有资料为用户分享产生,若发现您的权利被侵害,请联系客服邮件isharekefu@iask.cn,我们尽快处理。
本作品所展示的图片、画像、字体、音乐的版权可能需版权方额外授权,请谨慎使用。
网站提供的党政主题相关内容(国旗、国徽、党徽..)目的在于配合国家政策宣传,仅限个人学习分享使用,禁止用于任何广告和商用目的。
下载需要: 免费 已有0 人下载
最新资料
资料动态
专题动态
is_212655
暂无简介~
格式:doc
大小:69KB
软件:Word
页数:22
分类:文学
上传时间:2018-04-29
浏览量:27