首页 Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment

Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment

举报
开通vip

Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the EnlightenmentPeter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment Charles Wolfe comments on Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 2005) Sydney, HPS, 2007 Introduction thReill‘s initial claim is that the 1...

Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment
Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment Charles Wolfe comments on Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 2005) Sydney, HPS, 2007 Introduction thReill‘s initial claim is that the 18 century shouldn‘t be treated as ?mechanistic‘ (deterministic? quantitative?), in contrast to the classic, Adorno/Horkheimer view acc. to which Enlightenment = calculative rationalism. This s actually a point made in a variety of places (reprised p. 251f.). More original is his i suggestion that the response to mechanism breaks down into ?neomechanists‘ (Condorcet, D‘Alembert, Laplace, etc.) and ?vitalists‘ (p. 6). What about materialism, then? Someone like d‘Holbach doesn‘t quite fit this. Nor, earlier, does Toland. Nor La Mettrie (about whom Reill, quoting Vartanian [p. 269, n. 4], acknowledges that he ?organicizes‘ mechanism, but doesn‘t see that this might call into question his own 1opposition between mechanism and vitalism). Etc. But still, a helpful branching out picture. Similar reminder that there is kind of a Renaissance revival (p. 7). That is, similar modification of some of the received view. It is important for the historiography of vitalism that Reill locates both vitalism and ?neomechanism‘ within a skeptical framework — i.e., given the ―mid- th18-century critique of hypothetical thinking‖ (p. 5), which carries the Enlightenment away from system-rationalism as in the previous century, two fundamental strategies arise ―to satisfy the objections raised by the skeptical critique of reductive rationalism and uniformity‖ (p. 6): ―neomechanism‖ (as described above) and the view Reill calls ―Enlightenment vitalism‖ (ibid.). Thus, ―True to the skeptical critique of causation and forces, vitalists agreed that active life forces could not be seen directly, nor could they be measured‖ (p. 8; the general point is repeated at the end of the book, p. 252). I don‘t think other scholars (Rey, Duchesneau, Williams) have seen this. Connects 1 Also strange comment that Leibniz‘s notion of ―living machines‖ provided ―the basis for La Mettrie‘s attack upon a strict constructionist definition of organization in Man a Machine‖ (pp. 61-62): in fact La Mettrie is nothing of a Leibnizian (unlike Diderot), and it‘s not clear what ―constructionist‖ means here. However, it makes sense to say, as Roselyne Rey does in her history of vitalism in France, that Leibniz was its major philosophical influence. 1 obviously to the ?Newtonian analogy‘ theme. And makes vitalism seem like rather less of a metaphysics. This enables Reill, then, to claim that ?vitalism‘ is a better category — for the historian, presumably — than the binary opposition between mechanism and organicism (p. 11). I‘m not sure I totally see this, but it‘s clear that in classic works on the period, notably Roger (and in a different way, Canguilhem) there is far too much polarization of this sort (as noted also by Gaukroger with regard to Descartes). Of course, the vitalists themselves indulge in a good deal of polarization. And he doesn‘t just want to focus on some isolated figures, vitalists; ―my claims are much stronger‖ (p. 10): to define a figure called ?Enlightenment Vitalism‘ as a key representative figure, and one which is not an ideal type but a real type (p. 11). Nice point — at least one I agree with, and which runs counter to a lot of German scholarship (slightly partisan): Naturphilosophie is not the logical culmination of vitalism. ―Rather than seeing Naturphilosophie as vitalism‘s logical conclusion, I interpret it as its negation, as a thoroughgoing critique of the epistemological, methodological, and linguistic assumptions that undergirded Enlightenment Vitalism‖ (p. 14; restated p. 235). In a nutshell, Naturphilosophie seeks to overcome mediation and assert unity, community, etc., whereas vitalism is about mediation (not least between mechanism and organicism). (Think of split between Goethe and Diderot.) Recalling the skeptical motif, Reill claims (rightly I think) that ―The Naturphilosophen shunted aside the late Enlightenment‘s epistemological modesty, branding it timid and sterile, replacing it with an epistemological aggressiveness‖ (p. 209), of which Novalis is characteristic (one shouldn‘t disdain hypotheses, and one shouldn‘t limit oneself to an empiricist method). Reill returns to this distinction later on, and refers to the frequent invocation of Naturphilosophie as the ?other‘ of Enlightenment (which he doesn‘t disagree with). But his story changes the Manichean opposition between a ?bad‘ Enlightenment and a ?good‘, holistic Naturphilosophie by putting vitalism at centre stage, and insisting that it is not to be assimilated to Naturphilosophie and/or Romanticism. Granted, ―there is no doubt that Romantic Naturphilosophie could not have been constructed without concepts generated by Enlightenment vitalists‖ (p. 200). But ―in its goals, assumptions and conclusions, Romantic Naturphilosophie differed radically from Enlightenment vitalism‖ (ibid.), in its intellectual and scientific agenda – even if the critique of mechanism is an important shared theme. (One might say that vitalism 2 does not try and reject science and create a ?counter-science‘ in the largest sense possible, as Naturphilosophie does.) Prologue On the von Humboldt brothers. Unity of art and science, ?language of nature‘ (Jordanova), a kind of unity which is the opposite of the split between Natur- and Geisteswissenschaften. In this sense they are indeed like Diderot and various Enlightenment thinkers, 2 – for whom at least of the more naturalistic variety – not Rousseau, for instance investigations into Nature and into culture are part of one unified project (although 3then one runs into the ?Linnaean‘ problem of the place of man in a natural system, as e.g. in the pathos of the article ?Encyclopédie‘, by Diderot: One consideration above all must not be lost sight of, and that is that if man or the thinking, contemplating being is banished from the surface of the earth, this moving and sublime spectacle of nature becomes nothing but a sad and mute scene. The universe is dumb; silence and night overtake it. Everything changes into a vast solitude where unobserved phenomena occur in a manner dark and mute. It is the presence of man that makes the existence of beings interesting; and what could we better have in view in the history of those beings, than to yield to this consideration? Why not introduce man into our opus, as he is placed in the universe? Why not make of him a common center? Is there some point in infinite space from which we could more advantageously originate the immense lines which we propose to extend to all other points? What stirring and agreeable reaction of those beings towards 4man, and of man toward them, would not result? 5This is part of what is interesting in the project of ?natural history‘.) Point, again, that this is part of the Enlightenment, not a ?counter- Enlightenment‘ (Hermeticism etc.) and/or a ?proto-Romanticism‘ (pp. 28-29). (See the comment above about vitalism versus Naturphilosophie.) And then perhaps there are various Enlightenments (a banality, but one uttered here as a quotation of S. 2 Thus it seems odd to me to locate Rousseau within the genre of natural history as Reill does (p. 63 & 276, n. 112): Rousseau is an ardent anti-materialist, and the natural history program is, in the main, a materialist program. 3 As Phillip Sloan puts it, ―The central issue in anthropological theory of the period concerned the status of man in the growing taxonomic systematization of nature... Linnaeus had triggered the problem by his inclusion of man among the Quadrupeda in the order Anthropomorpha, along with the apes and sloths‖ (Sloan, ―Buffon, German biology, and the historical interpretation of biological species,‖ British Journal for the History of Science 12 (1979), p. 124). 4 Diderot, s.v. ―Encyclopédie,‖ in Encyclopédie, vol. V, 641c; trans. Philip Stewart (modified), in Encyclopedia of Diderot and D’Alembert, collaborative translation project ()). 5 A point made in Georges Gusdorf‘s Les sciences humaines et la pensée occidentale, V: Dieu, la nature et l’homme au siècle des Lumières (Paris: Payot, 1972) and more recently by Emma Spary in her contribution to The Sciences in Enlightened Europe, ed. Clark, Golinski, Schaffer (Chicago, 1999). 3 Shapin). — My reaction to this, at least initially, is that the older idea of ?national‘ Enlightenments might not be so bad after all, thinking about vitalism. That is, instead of Reill‘s vision in which there is a vitalistic Enlightenment which is German and French (and more), and it is also not just a marginal ?counter-Enlightenment‘, I might suggest that the vitalism of a Bordeu in France is very different from German vitalism, in its relation to materialism. (And here we get back to basic differences between Lumières and Aufklärung, regarding religion and the like.) ch. 1 (Buffon) p. 35f.: important distinction between mechanism and mathematical explanations. This plays out to some extent in the medical theories of the earlier part of this period (iatromechanism is not always formulated with regard to mathematics); and cf. the distinction between a ?quantitative approach‘ and ?mathematization‘ (see in thesis-nts ?Géométrie‘). p. 37, interesting point (from Margaret Jacobs) that mechanism gradually came to be associated with conservatism or at least orthodoxy. This is true in someone like Toland, and Diderot (cf. his ?anti-Newtonianism‘, in which chemistry plays an 6). But of course not true of Voltaire, or Maupertuis (who then seems to important role ?falsify‘ the category again: Maupertuis is a borderline materialist, interesting in living matter, with a proto-genetic theory; but he is also a Newtonian; one would then have to distinguish between a mechanistic line of development of Newtonianism – incl. D‘Alembert – and a more ?analogical‘ line of development, which gets one to 7vitalism. I am not proposing this as a hard and fast ?historical‘ claim but, for now, as a conceptual distinction.) p. 38: ―Hume‘s skeptical analysis of causation was but one instance . . . of the reevaluation of the mechanical natural philosophy.‖ — Sure… but having nothing to do with vitalism, or a vitalistic vision of Nature. (However the Humean program in ?moral science‘ or the ?science of human nature‘ may be said to transcend the Nature/culture split, too; and he‘s not much of a Newtonian despite older prevailing 8views.) 6th Reill notes, correctly, the importance of chemistry for vitalistic ideas in the 18 c. (pp. 67, 70). 7 But then there is Haller, who complicates this picture too, by being both a kind of supra-mechanist and employing Newtonian analogies to articulate physiological laws! 8 See Eric Schliesser‘s very helpful entry on Hume and Newtonianism in the Stanford Enc. of Philosophy: 4 Buffon‘s relation to mechanism etc. is partly more complicated than Reill says, because he was, at least in part of his career, something of a Newtonian: he translated the Vegetable Staticks (1727) by the ?medical Newtonian‘ Stephen Hales (on plant physiology and measurement of circulation of fluids; Statique des végétaux et analyse de l’air (1735)) – and, perhaps more importantly, Newton‘s Méthode des fluxions (1740). And he worked on the calculus of probabilities (as noted in fact by Reill, p. 41). Yet, like Diderot in particular, he has a rejection of mathematical abstractions in favor of the new, emerging life sciences (the idea that these are reducible to physics th-century view). The essay with which he which in turn is mathematizable is not an 18 begins the Histoire naturelle – a kind of prelude –, ―De la manière d‘étudier et de traiter l‘histoire naturelle,‖ speaks of the ―abuse [i.e. over-use, over-reliance on] of 9mathematical sciences,‖ and influenced Diderot‘s rejection of the foundational character of mathematics, and emphasizes that calculation is of limited value in 10presenting nature as a whole – species are just constructs. Indeed, a kind of constructivism is at work in his view of mathematics, since he describes mathematical truths as being merely ―definitional truths‖ (―vérités de définition‖), which as such are 11always ―exact and demonstrative,‖ but also ―abstract, intellectual and arbitrary.‖ Of course, one can also say that he is a ?mutated Newtonian‘, one who transfers the idea of force / gravity to the biological domain (as Reill notes, p. 43). On the status of human beings in Buffon (p. 39) and this kind of naturalistic view, see my comment above and footnote 2; and quote from Buffon given p. 53. The comments on the new emphasis on history in Buffon (p. 41) are interesting also with regard to Hume, and to the emergence of a ?historical‘ approach thto knowledge in the 18 century (from Bacon and Locke, actually); see work by Dario thPerinetti incl. his essay on the philosophy of history in the Cambridge Hist. of 18 c. Philosophy. p. 42, the comments on hermeticism etc. I think are wrong (cf. p. 84). It‘s true that Buffon is something like a vitalist, or at least has a theory (an important part of his overall theory) of living matter. But … (And furthermore, it‘s a bit awkward to make Buffon the source of Enlightenment vitalism. Of the major Montpellier vitalists, several, including Bordeu, had started to publish their works before Buffon‘s Histoire 9 Buffon, Œuvres philosophiques (Paris: PUF, 1954), p. 24a (hereafter OP). 10 A. Vartanian, Diderot and Descartes (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1953), p. 187. 11 OP, p. 24a. 5 th-century figures naturelle started to appear in 1749; and Reill leaves out [so far] 17 like Francis Glisson, who are certainly influences.) p. 54: I think it‘s wrong to equate Buffon with Vico‘s verum ipsum factum principle (which is to some extent of Baconian provenance). So: Buffon as ?Enlightenment vitalist‘. — Sure, but he is also a kind of reductionist. Unlike the self-proclaimed vitalists. But it‘s true that the distinction between living matter and dead matter is a key one for him, even if he also complicates the distinction. ch. 2 (Chemistry) … p. 75: I don‘t think it‘s right to equate Stahl and Buffon theoretically. Diderot is a mediating figure between the two, whose presence in this story would make it make more sense. p. 79 (aether). This is important. Materialization / substantialization of the world (also p. 93, ―substantialized force‖). Related to usage of concept of ?animal spirits‘, which is a medico-physiological concept with materialist philosophical overtones (a type of matter with animate properties). th p. 84: this claim – that late 18 c naturalism is about hidden things, thus incl. vitalism – is debatable (I mean just that, not that it‘s wrong, but it should be debated; on the one hand there is a kind of opacity and recognition that the naturalist doesn‘t deal with essences – Locke, Diderot, etc. – but on the other hand it‘s not an ?irrationalist‘ position either; can perhaps be seen in pragmatist terms; complicating the issue is the vitalist fondness, notably in Barthez, for the ?Newtonian analogy‘ which posits an unknown ?x‘, calls it ?vital force‘ and then seeks to develop an 12account of phenomena from it). — David: how is this really Newtonian? Where is the science? pp. 89-90, on ?oeconomy of nature‘. I agree this is an important theme. Notably from Linnaeus, who has a book of that title – De oeconomia naturae – that appears the same year as Buffon‘s HN, vol. 1 (1749). But this kind of emphasis on equilibrium is not something they all agree on. The more ?Epicurean‘, radical strand 12 On the latter idea, see TS Hall‘s important but rather opaque article ―On Biological Analogs of Newtonian Paradigms,‖ Phil. of Science (1968). 6 of Enlightenment thought emphasizes disorder and randomness; order as human projection. Chemistry. Nice line of Reill‘s: ―The subsumption of chemistry under the general categories of the mechanical laws of matter and motion had dethroned it from the preeminent position it once occupied in Renaissance and early modern natural philosophy‖ (p. 72). Boerhaave is interesting indeed here. Stahl also, inversely (but also complicated situation whereby chemistry is both the science that defines the difference between organic and inorganic bodies, and the science that threatens to nd-ortake away the specificity of the organic, in a kind of ?2der reductionism‘). — What about iatrochemistry? ch. 3 “Within the circle of organized life” p. 118, important to note (not original to Reill) that Montpellier vitalism takes as its targets both mechanism and animism. — This has interesting implications for the metaphysical, or non-metaphysical nature of this kind of vitalism, i.e., as I put it in thanother place, it means that 18 c. vitalism in France is a kind of 'Neither-Nor' which seeks to navigate in between the conceptual Charybdis and Scylla of Mechanism and Animism, the two competing models of the late 17th-early 18th century. Mechanism (in many forms: Descartes; Boerhaave; Borelli and Italian micro-anatomy; Hoffman) misses the distinctive features of living beings from a medical and physiological point of view (so the vitalist argument goes); Animism (chiefly Georg-Ernest Stahl) which relates all vital functions to an organizing principle called the Soul, does actually 'see' those distinctive features but accounts for them with an unwieldy metaphysics, etc. etc. It is important not to confuse vitalism with animism, as it really strives to find a intermediate way between these two positions. The latter point is probably the most important. Given that, what to make of vitalism in the period, then? We might claim it is more "heuristic" than "ontological"; its recurrent invocations of a Newtonian method by which one posits an 'x' to explain phenomena, rather than actually claiming there is an x = vital force with magical properties, go in this direction. We might also point to its 'patient-centred' approach, as a criticism of the disembodied, and 'atomistic' character of mechanistic physiology and medicine; it brings in a more temporal dimension. The latter aspect makes the "holistic" or "organismic" dimension of vitalism a bit more manageable, more 'pragmatic' and less 'metaphysical'. p. 121, mechanism (incl. Boerhaave) as target – certainly not for A. von Haller (as I‘ve noted earlier), arguably the greatest figure in the life sciences in the later thth?chunk‘ of the mid-18 century (I would have said ?the later 18 century but I noticed 7 that Reill names, perhaps legitimately, Blumenbach – Haller‘s successor in Göttingen – to this title; Haller is chiefly active 1740s-1775). Nor for La Mettrie. Similarly, note that mechanism is not a monolithic category by any means. Harvey ? Descartes ? Baglivi/Borelli ? Boerhaave, all of whom are ?mechanists‘ (as well as Boyle?). Boerhaave is quite happy to criticize Cartesian mechanism and to try and integrate other elements therein. There are also people like Claude Perrault (the brother of Charles who wrote the famous children‘s tales like Puss in Boots) or Fontenelle who combine mechanical and chemical models: Le Corps humain considéré par rapport à une infinité de différents mouvements volontaires qu‘il peut exécuter, est un assemblage prodigieux de Leviers tirés par des Cordes. Si on le regarde par rapport au mouvement des liqueurs qu‘il contient, c‘est un autre assemblage d‘une infinité de Tuyaux et de Machines Hydrauliques. Enfin si on l‘examine par rapport à la génération de ces mêmes liqueurs, c‘est encore un assemblage infini d‘Instruments, ou de Vaisseaux Chymiques, de Filtres, d‘Alambics, de Récipients, de Serpentins, etc. … Le plus grand appareil de Chimie qui soit dans tout le Corps humain, le plus merveilleux Laboratoire est dans le Cerveau. C‘est là que se tire du sang ce précieux Extrait, qu‘on appelle les Esprits, uniques moteurs matériels de toute la Machine du Corps. (Fontenelle, Histoire de l’Académie Royale des Sciences, 1707) Now, part of where mechanism gets ?complexified‘ is the nervous system. It‘s fine in Paduan anatomy to work on muscles, veins, bones; but (a) what actually is ?active‘ in the muscles? (Irritability – Whytt to Haller), and (b) what about the communication of impulses through the body (something Descartes tries famously to model in his Treatise on Man)? Notion of sympathy, for one thing (cf. e.g. Reill, p. 129 bottom, on 13Whytt; p. 140). Further comments on nervous system, p. 148f. Discuss concepts of ?organization‘ and ?animal economy‘ (both presented on p. 136). Organization we talked about. The point that didn‘t quite emerge is my claim that this concept might be more ?mechanism-friendly‘ than that of organism (which is ultimately a concept taken over and extended in German Romanticism / Naturphilosophie). As to ?animal economy‘, it‘s a tricky concept because some figures speak of it in mechanistic terms, such as Boerhaave (―Vocatur φυσιολ?γικη, ο?χονομ?α humana, 13 NB, although it has nothing to do with our topic: when Reill mentions Smith and Barthez on sympathy, p. 141, he is omitting Hume and Hutcheson. Sympathy‘s ?life‘ as a moral concept in Scottish moral thought is far more important than what Reill indicates. 8 14); but Mandeville, who studied in Leyden at the same time doctrina de usu partium‖ as Boerhaave, seems to distinguish the animal economy from mere ?structure‘, like vitalists will do, saying that the study of Harvey and Borelli helped him ―understand 15the Oeconomy as well as the Structure of the Body,‖ i.e. these are two distinct things. But in the main, it is an anti-mechanistic concept. Fifty-sixty years later, the Montpellier vitalist physician Ménuret de Chambaud declares quite bluntly, in his article for the Encyclopédie entitled precisely ―Œconomie Animale,‖ that with the mechanists, le corps humain devint entre leurs mains une machine extrêmement composée, ou plutôt un magasin de cordes, leviers, poulies & autres instrumens de méchanique, & ils pensoient que le but général de tous ces ressorts étoit de concourir au mouvement progressif du sang, le seul absolument nécessaire à la vie […]. On crut que le mouvement s‘y faisoit, suivant les lois ordinaires qui ont lieu dans toutes les machines inorganiques ; on traita géométriquement le corps humain ; on calcula avec la derniere sévérité tous les degrés de force requis pour les différentes actions, les dépenses qui s‘en faisoient, &c. mais tous ces calculs qui ne pouvoient que varier prodigieusement, n‘éclaircirent point l‘oeconomie animale. On ne fit pas même attention à la structure organique du corps humain qui est la source de ses principales propriétés (Enc. XI, 364b). Indeed, it seems that there was a school of ?Hippocratic physicians‘ in Paris in the thlater 16 century, including Louis Duret, who spoke of an ―oeconomia naturalis, 16vitalis et animalis‖ and referred back, not just to Hippocrates but to Paracelsus. If we recall the Linnaean fondness for the vocabulary of ?oeconomy‘ (e.g. oeconomia naturalis), this should tell us that animal economy is connected to the old analogy between microcosm and macrocosm. (Of course, for Paracelsus, even such a term as anatomia referred to the correspondence between stars and the body ; cf images of the th?zodiac man‘ – type that term into Google Images and you‘ll see.) A 19-century medical dictionary defines the term as meaning ―the set of laws governing the organization of animals and plants. It was Charlton [=Charleton? CW] who used this expression in this sense first, in 1658, but since Haller the term ?economy‘ has also 14 Boerhaave, Praelectiones academicae in proprias institutiones rei medicae, ed. Haller, Venice, 1753, vol. I, ? 33, p. 48. 15st Mandeville, A Treatise of the Hypochondriack and Hysterick Diseases, in Three Dialogues (1 ed. nd1711), 2 corrected ed. (London: Tonson, 1730; reprint, Delmar, N.Y.: Scholars‘ Reprints, 1976), p. 21; later on (p. 75) he distinguishes between ―anatomy and animal economy‖ (see also p. 143). 16 Bernard Balan, ? Premières recherches sur l‘origine et la formation du concept d‘économie animale ?, p. 301. 9 17 All of been used to designate the sum of parts which comprise organized beings.‖this ends up being quite bound up with Stahl and his ?animism‘. — speaking of Stahl (p. 123f.), here are some comments by other scholars on his notion of organism, as opposed to mechanism: the significant feature is neither the laws of physics or chemistry, nor the adherence of phenomena to the laws of motion. We may take for granted that natural phenomena obey these laws and that this constitutes mechanism. The truly significant question is whether the phenomena exhibit a goal or direction or end. If so, then we deal with organism and the mechanical activities, serving as means to that end, are 18instruments. The mechanical configuration is then an organon. and: When Stahl writes about the organism, he does not mean a body ?endowed with organs‘. ?Organic‘ to him means a coordinated and integrated whole, the ?organism‘, adjusting to its environment both on a conscious and unconscious level (sensually, emotionally and mentally) with immediate physiological results. Thus Stahl‘s medical theory is essentially a theory of a holistic, self-determined ?organism‘. His thunderstanding of the organism is not equivalent to 19-century vitalism because he did not centre his theory on the function of specific organs in the body. His definition of the organism is encompassing, equating ?life‘ with the ability of the whole organism to organise change. The ?organ‘ of perception is not somatic at all ; it is the sum of all perceptual processes, and he calls this the soul. . . . ?The life of the body which is organic‘ expresses what Stahl was trying to achieve : it is nothing less than a substantiated theory (based on case observations and medical logic) that the soul and the body are a unity. Life is organic and life is the active soul working within the structures and substances of the body. Its limit, but not its essence, 19is the body. As to Haller (p. 130f.): importance of concepts of irritability/sensitivity. p. 132, bottom: Bordeu vs Haller on irritability. This is a bit obscure in general, and possibly of limited interest to people who aren‘t historians of vitalism. Indeed, some of it amounts to rivalry on Bordeu‘s part, in relation to Haller. But philosophically there is an important point here: Bordeu is reconfiguring this property so it is a basic property of matter (and denying the functional-dualist distinction between irritab and sensib, in Haller; same denial in Barthez [same rivalry], p. 141). In other words, he is creating a direct link between physiology and philosophical materialism. 17th Littré & Robin, Dictionnaire de médecine (Paris, 12 ed., 1865), art. ―Économie,‖ p. 486. 18 L.S. King, The Philosophy of Medicine, pp.146-147. 19 J. Geyer-Kordesch, ? Stahl‘s Radical Pietist Medicine and its Influence on the German Enlightenment ?, in A. Cunningham & R. French, eds., The Medical Enlightenment of the Eighteenth Century, pp. 69, 77. 10 p. 138: ―this skepticism…led Enlightenment vitalists to reintroduce the idea of occult qualities into their work‖ — cf. our earlier discussion about Newtonian models, and Reill‘s gloss on Barthez, p. 143. Indeed I‘d disagree with this statement. Part of why I don‘t quite accept his whole idea of ?Enlightenment vitalism‘. p. 146: confusing usage of a priori and a posteriori by Blumenbach? ch. 4, „Metamorphoses of Change? Surprising that Harvey coins the word ?epigenesis‘ (p. 57). Should be more discussion of this term and its ramifications (consider cases of Kant, Diderot). Other question (Alan): after Harvey on epigenesis, why are there all these debates in the next century? Why preformationism again as a doctrine? Epilogue Foucault (p. 255); irony that Reill doesn‘t see challenge Foucault poses to his project, re ?Life‘. Strange idea to begin and end the book with analysis of von Humboldts. Partial connection lying in Reill‘s (odd?) claim that the vitalist view essentially treats nature as history, or at least as having a history. (In some vague Goldsteinian way one can see how this might be.) And indeed the fusion of nature and history is the Von Humboldt theme. Still, impression of disparate material put together. Reill certainly seems to know a lot about both the French and German Enlightenments, though. But how is it really put together? Doesn‘t he paper over a lot of crucial differences between what it might mean to be a vitalist in France and in Germany? In 1749 in France and in 1780 in Germany? On the other hand, his point about Naturphilosophie (that it has falsely been identified with vitalism and should be decoupled from it) seems to indicate he is not just a ?lumper‘ (but a splitter). What about England then? And earlier vitalism? But his book aims to revise the picture of the Enlightenment. 11 * * * NB Cuvier has a brilliant, devastating critique of Naturphilosophie in his Rapport historique sur les progrès des sciences naturelles (1810), II, ? Histoire naturelle ?, p. 235. Particular themes: * Modification of notion of cause and effect (p. 7 bottom). Cf. notion of ?cercle d‘action‘ in vitalist medicine, as discussed in Wolfe and Terada, ?Animal Economy‘, forthcoming in Science in Context (2008). * Synergy (p. 7 / 259 n. 20, p. 126). Quibbles: — p. 259, n. 21, careful not to get confused re. Kant, who despite his fondness for Stahl etc., is by no means a vitalist (compare Spinoza) – indeed, cf. what Reill describes about Kielmeyer (cf. Sciences-nts) in relation to Kant; — Goethe is not the same sort of thinker as Bordeu at all! (p. 138) — In general I‘m surprised at the absence of Condillac from the story, as he is the main (certainly the first) theorist of signs in the Enlightenment, a prominent sensationist … but not a vitalist. see also: S. Gaukroger on Reill on vitalism and mechanism in Enlightenment, 12
本文档为【Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment】,请使用软件OFFICE或WPS软件打开。作品中的文字与图均可以修改和编辑, 图片更改请在作品中右键图片并更换,文字修改请直接点击文字进行修改,也可以新增和删除文档中的内容。
该文档来自用户分享,如有侵权行为请发邮件ishare@vip.sina.com联系网站客服,我们会及时删除。
[版权声明] 本站所有资料为用户分享产生,若发现您的权利被侵害,请联系客服邮件isharekefu@iask.cn,我们尽快处理。
本作品所展示的图片、画像、字体、音乐的版权可能需版权方额外授权,请谨慎使用。
网站提供的党政主题相关内容(国旗、国徽、党徽..)目的在于配合国家政策宣传,仅限个人学习分享使用,禁止用于任何广告和商用目的。
下载需要: 免费 已有0 人下载
最新资料
资料动态
专题动态
is_721103
暂无简介~
格式:doc
大小:78KB
软件:Word
页数:0
分类:
上传时间:2018-04-15
浏览量:2